The New Atheists frequently will appeal to Saint David
(Hume) in their rejection of miracles. In this article, in brief, I will
present why I find Hume’s On Miracles to be fundamentally flawed on numerous
levels. More can be said on Hume than what I present here however so please, if
you have any questions leave them in the comment section and I will do my best
to reply in a timely manner.
1. His
primary argument relies on what he has already said is impossible in the first
half of On Miracles, that is, the logical use of induction. Hume spent the
first half of On Miracles refuting the notion of induction only to turn around
and use it (and a pretty vague concept of it at that) to attempt to disprove
miracles.
His basic argument
against induction is that there is no guarantee that the future will be like
the past. Partly due to his thoughts on causality, Hume says that just because
every time the cue ball hits the billiard ball in the past and the billiard
ball moved, we do not know that such a causal correlation will occur in the
future. Maybe tomorrow when they collide, the cue ball will be turned into an
egg. Every morning when we get out of bed our feet land on solid flooring. But
maybe tomorrow our floor will be viscous and we will sink right through it. We
can see more clearly Hume’s problem with induction by looking at a simple
argument:
P1) Every jelly bean I have eaten from the jar tastes like licorice.
P1) Every jelly bean I have eaten from the jar tastes like licorice.
P2) Therefore all
the jelly beans in the jar will taste like licorice.
The question is,
can we ever be justified in positively or certainly claiming P2? Hume despairs
and says no.
Now, I actually
think that defenses of induction are possible and disagree with Hume that we
can never make inductive claims like P2, especially considering that I think
one of the main differences between induction and deduction is varied degrees
of certainty. So I think induction can be reframed such that the conclusions
are not statements of certainty but rather something like P3 “Therefore it is
plausible (to a varied degree) that all the jelly beans in the jar will taste
like licorice.”
Here we can also
bring in things like justification. What if there are 5000 jelly beans and P1
is true, but I have only eaten 5. Would I be justified in asserting P3? Not
really. But if I ate 3000 then maybe or if I ate 9 out of only 10 then probably
yes.
One of the
inductive problems for Hume however is that he does deny
induction. And yet when he begins to discuss miracles, one of his arguments is
that we have the universal experience of no miracles occurring and therefore we
should conclude no miracles will occur in the future. Yet this is only possible
if we say something like,
P1) No miracles
have occurred in the past.
P2) Therefore no
miracles will occur in the future.
Besides the fact
that this is not really even a syllogism where the conclusion is drawn from
true premises, it would rely on some principle of induction in order for it to
work. Something Hume has already said we should not allow.
Another inductive
problem is that another one of Hume’s arguments, that miracles cannot happen
because they violate the laws of nature, assumes that natural laws have been or
will always be the same. Think of the billiard ball. If Hume wants to deny
induction by saying that the billiard ball isn’t guaranteed to move simply
because it has always behaved that way in the past, then how is he able to say
that a natural law cannot be violated in the future because they have not been
violated in the past? One possible recourse would be to say that laws of nature
just are things that are inviolable. Yet again, all he is doing is assuming
that because natural laws have been the kinds of things that are inviolable in
the past that they are guaranteed to be inviolable in the future.
And before you go
on to say that these are facts that can be observed through science, you have
to realize that you are still only appealing to induction – science has lead to
true knowledge in the past, therefore it will lead to true knowledge in the
present and the future. It is still circular and still relies on induction.
Now, you may
resolve the issue by simply agreeing with me that Hume is wrong on his
rejection of induction and therefore be free to make his argument against
miracles. However, it must be stated explicitly which position you will take.
Do you deny the 1st half of On Miracles or the 2nd? Do
you deny his arguments against induction or do you deny his arguments against
miracles? We simply cannot have both.
2. The
next problem is that of the utter circularity of the probabilistic argument
against miracles. Basically he says that we can know that miracles do not occur
because we have the universal experience of no miracles occurring. Yet can he
know such universal experience? Well we can only know that there is universal
experience of no miracles occurring if we know that all the reports of them are
false. But we can only know that they are all false if we know that no miracles
have occurred. The syllogism would be as follows,
P1) We know that miracles
do not occur because we have universal experience of no miracles occurring.
P2) We know that we
have such universal experience or no miracles occurring because we know that
all reports of miracles are false.
P3) We know that all
reports of miracles are false because we know that no miracle has occurred.
That is a circle of the most vicious kind.
Ok, those are the obvious problems. The next ones become a bit more complicated.
3. Next
is Hume’s assertion that miracles are impossible because they just are
violations of the inviolable natural laws. We have already seen that this poses
a problem for his objection to induction, but now we will see that it also
presupposes the truth of naturalism – which is his intended conclusion.
In order for this
objection to work, we must accept two of Hume’s definitions, neither of which I
think we should. The first is the definition of a natural law as inviolable.
This seems a bizarre stance to take in modern times considering that most
scientists and philosophers of science would define natural laws merely as
descriptions of the normative behaviors of the natural world. All of science,
and indeed natural laws, function on the assumption of “caeteris
paribus” or “all things being equal.” Science and natural law are only
descriptions of what happens when nature goes about its merry way without any
interruption, injection of new information, or exertion of some other force,
natural or otherwise.
This is where C.S. Lewis’
famous example of arithmetic comes in. I do not say the bank thief who robbed
my bank broke the laws of arithmetic because the ledgers do not balance, but
rather the laws of California. The laws of arithmetic have not been violated,
new circumstances arose. Not all things were equal.
In fact I noticed
something quite ironic a while back. This exact defense is used by
evolutionists against creationists who assert that the 2nd Law of
Thermodynamics makes evolution impossible. They claim that because evolution is
the tendency toward increased complexity and that the 2nd Law is
that all nature tends toward entropy, that evolution violates the 2nd
Law and is therefore not possible. Besides that this is not the best
understanding of either evolution or thermodynamics, evolutionists often point
out the same response we should give to Hume. Evolutionists quite rightly point
out that other factors are at work that lead to less entropy. That is, the 2nd
Law is not violated, it is superseded. The influence of outside actors can
override the normal operation of the natural world. Like before, it is not all
things being equal.
This leads us to
Hume’s definition of a miracle just as a violation of a law of nature. Why must
we accept that definition? Why can it not simply be the influence of an outside
actor overriding the normal operation of the natural world. We can think of
resurrection as an example of this. Many anti-theists seem to have a love
affair with calling it a “zombie” apocalypse but that is really just a
deficient way of understanding it. Imagine that I died of cardiac arrest right
now and was rushed the hospital. The doctors would try CPR and defibrillation
on me and hopefully my heart would suddenly start again. Now, do we say that the doctors
have violated the law that dead bodies stay dead? (There is no actual natural
law to this effect but I think it is a common enough belief that dead bodies stay
dead.) Well no. We recognize that if I was truly dead (and not just swooning or
something), and all things being equal, no one did anything I would have stayed
dead. But there was the intervention of an outside actor, the infusion of new
information (in the form of energy), etc. The law was not violated, the
circumstances simply did not remain “caeteris paribus”.
Yet if we allow for
doctors to revive patients dead for a short period of time, why is it logically
impossible (for that is Hume’s contention) that a being like God could not
simply do something of the sort for people dead for a longer period of time? It
would not be the violation of natural law, but merely the intervention of an
outside actor inserting new information into the system.
The only recourse
to deny this as logically possible, is if one is already precommitted to
naturalism. That is, that no such being or action can possibly exist. But then
one is arguing from the premise that no such action can possibly occur to the
conclusion that no such action can possibly occur. It simply begs the question.
Therefore this argument of Hume’s fails.
4. The
final argument I would like to look at is his argument from probability – “that
no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of
such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the fact, which
it endeavors to establish”.
Firstly, it should
be pointed out that this is not actually one of Hume’s arguments. It is set up
in Part 1 of the book as the ground work for his later argument. It is not an
argument against miracles (as many try to cast it now) but rather is a
contention about the kind of evidence that should be permissible in the
demonstration that miracles do or do not occur.
Hume continues,
“(T)here is not to be found, in all history, any miracle attested by a sufficient number of Men of such unquestioned good sense, education, and learning as to serve us against all delusion in themselves; of such undaunted integrity as to place themselves beyond all suspicion of any design to deceive others; of such credit and reputation in the eyes of mankind as to have a great deal to lose in case of their being detected in any falsehood, and at the same time attesting facts performed in such a public manner and in so celebrated a part of the world as to render the detection unavoidable...”
Well one could
argue that it has been found that there is in history an event which
was attested by a sufficient number (what counts as sufficient for Hume?) of
eyewitnesses, who give no sign of lack of good sense, education (how much is
needed to know – “Hey… he was dead and entombed… and now he is eating fish with
us”), we have no reason to think that they intentionally deceived others
(especially since they gained nothing from their testimony and did actually
“have a great deal to lose incase of their being detected of any falsehood,”
and were even more disadvantaged in some brutal ways for even asserting it. Not
to mention that they did assert it publically and allowed for contradiction even
though none came.
In fact Hume
states,
“There surely never was a greater number of miracles ascribed to one person, than those which were lately said to have been wrought in France upon the tomb of AbbĂ© Paris, the famous Jansenist, with whose sanctity the people were so long deluded. The curing of the sick, giving hearing to the deaf, and sight to the blind, were everywhere talked of as the usual effects of that holy sepulchre. But what is more extraordinary, many of the miracles were immediately proved upon the spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses of credit and distinction, in a learned age, and on the most eminent theatre that is now in the world. Nor is this all. A relation of them was published and dispersed everywhere; nor were the Jesuits, though a learned body, supported by the civil magistrates, and determined enemies to those opinions, in whose favour the miracles were said to have been wrought, ever able distinctly to refute or detect them. Where shall we find such a number of circumstances, agreeing to the corroboration of one fact? And what have we to oppose to such a cloud of witnesses, but the absolute impossibility, or miraculous nature of the events which they relate? And this, surely, in the eyes of all reasonable people, will alone be regarded as a sufficient refutation.”
This is just one of
several examples that he gives where all of his criteria have ostensibly
been met. And yet he goes on to say he would "still reply that the knavery
and folly of men are such common phenomena" that he would rather believe
that it was a conspiracy than a miracle. So, ironically even Hume basically
admits that his standard is so high that even in his most modern time if all
the criteria were met, that he would still reject it! Why? Because it’s just
impossible. It just has to be wrong and that his just saying so should “be regarded
as a sufficient refutation” to “all reasonable people.” Well that’s not an
argument. It’s mere presumption and circular reasoning.
John Earman's
principle in his book Hume’s Abject Failure is much the same as my own:
"An epistemology that does not allow for the possibility that evidence,
whether from eyewitness testimony or from other sources, can establish the
credibility of a UFO landing, a walking on water, or a resurrection is
inadequate." Basically, there is the appearance of reason in the standard
but when it is examined it is intentionally set up so as to be impossible to
appease. The standard itself is on principle that no evidence could
ever meet the requirement and thus no fact could ever be brought to bear
against the truth of naturalism.
No eyewitness will
ever be credible enough. No experiment that has the outcome of a miracle would
ever be more likely than conspiracy, etc. It is not reasonable, it is
presumptive. It is the empiricist equivalent of a fanatical conspiracy theorist
riddled with confirmation bias. Now, I am skeptical about a great many things.
I think skepticism is healthy. But skepticism that is so extreme, almost
Cartesian, cannot be helpful in anyway. Try to convince someone who has their
mind made up that we are living in the Matrix that we are not and you will be
frustrated indeed. There is nothing you could ever point to in this world that
would prove otherwise because everything will be infused with the air of
conspiracy. Everything would simply be a part of the construct.
To illustrate this,
let us imagine that we live in a universe where miracles have in fact occurred.
If we accept Hume’s epistemological standard then we would have set up a
standard, by assuming naturalism, whereby we could not only not know a
fundamental fact about the universe, but where we would actually be positively
irrational if we believed what was actually true. It seems to me that any
standard where by true knowledge = irrationalism has a fundamental flaw
somewhere contained within its assumptions.
Another problem is
one that even Hume’s contemporaries noticed. They gave the example of a Prince
from a tropical land who had never seen ice. By Hume’s line of reasoning, the
Prince would be just as validated in not believing in ice as the skeptic is for
not believing in miracles. Hume tried to counteract this by saying that just
because the Prince might be reasonable for denying the existence of ice, there
were other humans who did experience ice and therefore it is reasonable for
them to believe in ice (and indeed for others to take their word for it.) The
problem here is that this just reduces down to a subjective argument from
experience – a kind of argument skeptics are loathe to endorse. If we accept
this principle, then the atheist must accept the Christian’s statement of
belief based on religious experience as a reasonable means of knowledge. They
might have no experience of God, but others have. The prince had not
experienced ice, but others had.
It is further
undermined by Earman who responds by saying that if this is so, then if homo
sapiens arose in Africa, "there was a stage in human history where the
total collective experience of the species coincided in relevant respects"
with that of the prince who lived in a tropical climate. This means that we
could literally echo Hume’s argument that we have the universal experience of “no
ice” and therefore any testimony about ice existing in the future are more
likely to be false.
Hume then went on to attempt
to argue that for the prince, the existence if ice could possibly be deduced by
analogy to something else. He stated that the Prince could come to believe in a
solid form of water simply by a positive analogy from other phase changes in
water. Earman makes a good point in one
of his footnotes: "If one sees a positive analogy for a solid form of
water in other phase changes, why not see a positive analogy for resurrection
in near death experiences, catatonic states, and the like?"
I will end with Earman's
summary which is important as a critique even in the midst of him praising Hume
for at least identifying an important problem and dealing with it in an
interesting manner:
“In 'Of Miracles,' Hume pretends to stand on philosophical high ground, hurling down thunderbolts against miracles stories. The thunderbolts are supposed to issue from general principles about inductive inference and the credibility of eyewitness testimony. But when these principles are made explicit and examined under the lens of Bayesianism, they are found to be either vapid, specious, or at variance with actual scientific practice...[Hume] was able to create the illusion of a powerful argument by maintaining ambiguities in his claims against miracles, by the use of forceful prose and confident pronouncements, and by liberal doses of sarcasm and irony...I find it ironic that so many readers of Hume's essay have been subdued by its eloquence...No doubt this generous treatment stems in part from the natural assumption that someone of Hume's genius must have produced a powerful set of considerations. But I suspect that in more than a few cases it also involves the all too familiar phenomenon of endorsing an argument because the conclusion is liked. There is also the understandable, if deplorable, desire to sneer at the foibles of the less enlightened -- and how much more pleasurable the sneering if it is sanctioned by a set of philosophical principles!”
No comments:
Post a Comment